The Role of Culture in Moral Development
Daniel Pekarsky, PhD
Professor, Educational Policy Studies
University of Wisconsin-Madison
Professor, Educational Policy Studies
University of Wisconsin-Madison
Introduction
The title of this discussion, "The Role of Culture in
Moral Development", points to two different, albeit inter-related,
questions: first, what role does culture play in moral development?; and second, what is the proper responsibility
of a culture in guiding the moral growth of its members? This paper
does not systematically explore what the proper role of a culture is in
the area of moral growth, and it recognizes that precisely what this
role should be is rightly subject to debate. At the same time, it takes
it for granted that because, as I will discuss, the social universe that
children encounter inevitably, and for better or for worse, influences
their moral growth, a community needs to view itself as responsible for
the moral growth of its members. This paper argues that while this
communal responsibility cannot be adequately discharged through
special-purpose institutions like schools, such institutions, if thought
of in the right way, may be capable of playing a significant role in
the process of moral growth. The reasons for this view will emerge
through our inquiry into the role that, intended or not, culture does
play in the moral development of its members. Before embarking on this
inquiry, and because terms like "culture" and "moral development" are
far from self- explanatory, let me preface my remarks with a few
comments concerning how I will be interpreting these terms in the
context of this paper.
I will be using the term "culture" in a fairly intuitive
and very broad sense to denote the totality of the social environment
into which a human being is born and in which he/she lives. Culture in
this sense includes the community's institutional arrangements (social,
political, and economic) but also its forms of art and knowledge, the
assumptions and values embedded in its practices and organization, its
images of heroism and villainy, it various systems of ideas, its forms
of work and recreation, and so forth.
I turn now to the concept of moral development. By
"moral development" I will be referring to the process through which a
human being acquires sensibilities, attitudes, beliefs, skills, and
dispositions that render him or her a morally mature or adequate human
being. Of course, this definition is, at best, a mere shell, empty of
content; for it tells us nothing about what those sensibilities,
attitudes, beliefs, skills, and dispositions are that mark one
as a morally adequate human being. There are two reasons for leaving
this matter open. The first is that it may be presumptuous to present a
positive account of this matter too quickly in the face of what we all
know, namely, that the character of this moral content is a subject of
rich debate across the whole of human history down to our own time. The
second is that, for present purposes, it may be unnecessary to offer a
positive account of the content of a desirable moral character. That
is, much that I intend to say here does not require settling, even
tentatively, on an account of a morally desirable or adequate character.
At the same time, lest this account be affected in ways I don't
recognize by the moral concerns at work in my own thinking on moral
development, let me intuitively identify some of these concerns.
Briefly, these concerns grow out of reflection on two matters: the Nazi
Holocaust and kindred phenomena, on the one hand, and, on the other
hand, social psychological and other research suggesting that the
perpetrators of the atrocities our century has witnessed may not be as
different from "the rest of us" as "we" might want to believe.
Attention to such matters has led me to attend to those features of
moral growth that are associated with two kinds of sensibilities,
attitudes, principles, and dispositions: those that enable us to resist
dehumanizing other human beings in thought and conduct in precisely
those situations when there might be a disposition to engage in such
dehumanization; and those that enable us to view ourselves as
responsible for preventing such dehumanization when we see it going on.
While this account of the moral domain is neither fully clear nor
complete, it may help to illuminate the background the informs my
approach to problem of moral growth and cultural context. Though I am
doubtful that the approach would be substantially different were my
interest in the subject grounded in other kinds of moral concerns, this
possibility needs to be allowed for.
Against this background, my purpose in this paper is to
use a powerful classical perspective on the role of culture in mediating
our moral experience and development to highlight a difficult human
problem. I then proceed to sketch out what might be called a classical
American response to this problem, a response, strongly associated with
John Dewey, that gives pride of place to educating institutions. While
this response is not, to my mind, as compelling as the problem it
addresses, I conclude by suggesting that, despite its possible
shortcomings, we should avoid prematurely dismissing it. I turn now to
the characterization of the problem.
Ancient Wisdom on a Perennial Problem
Both Jerusalem and Athens - the culture of the ancient
Israelites and the culture of the ancient Greeks, each of which has
substantially influenced contemporary Western civilization - speak
instructively concerning the role that culture plays in the moral life
of human beings. Commenting in Hellenistic times on the Biblical verse,
"Noah was a righteous man, and perfect in his generation," Rabbinic
commentators intimate two very different interpretations:1
"In his generation, R[abbi] Yochanan pointed out, but not in other generations. However, according to Resh Lakish, the verse intimates that even in his generation Noah was a righteous man, all the more so in other generations."On the first of these interpretations, Noah is only relatively righteous; that is, relative to his perverse contemporaries, he looks very good, but this does not mean that he would be judged good by any absolute standard. This interpretation coheres with other rabbinic commentaries which emphasize that Abraham was, morally speaking, far superior to Noah.2
The other interpretation, however, is more germane to our
topic. According to Resh Lakish, if Noah was capable of remaining
righteous in the midst of the unbridled perversity that surrounded him
on all sides, how much more so would he have been in a community in
which morally adequate conduct was the norm! At work in Resh Lakish's
observation is the insight that our moral outlook and conduct are, in
the normal course of events, strongly influenced by the culture that
surrounds us; and that, therefore, the person who is capable of arriving
at moral insights that go beyond - and indeed defy - what is the norm
in his or her culture, or who is able to maintain integrity in the
midst of a perverse community, is a most extra-ordinary human being --
much more so than the one who behaves well in the midst of a community
in which the norm is good conduct.
Interestingly, Plato expresses a very similar idea in a famous passage of the Republic:
It is noteworthy that in this passage Plato identifies three critical variables that jointly give rise to the moral character of a human being: native traits (or what we might call genetic endowment or pre-dispositions); early childhood experience; and, finally, the surrounding culture. For our purposes, Plato's reference to innate traits that bear on our moral development, while interesting, is not immediately relevant. More relevant are the points pertaining to early childhood experience and to the power of the surrounding culture.Is not the same principle true of the mind, Adeimantus: if their early training is bad, the most gifted turn out the worst...Or do you hold the popular belief that, here and there, certain young men are demoralized by the instructions of some individual sophist? Does that sort of influence amount to much? Is not the public itself the greatest of all sophists, training up young and old, men and women alike, into the most accomplished specimens of the character it desires to produce?Whenever the populace crowds together at any public gathering, in the Assembly, the law courts, the theatre or the camp, and sits there clamouring its approval or disapproval, both alike excessive, of whatever is being said or done....In such a scene what do you suppose will be a young man's state of mind? What sort of private instruction will have given him the strength to hold up against the force of such a torrent, or will save him from being swept away down the stream, until he accepts all their notions of right and wrong, does as they do, and comes to be just such a man as they are? And I have said nothing of the most powerful engines of persuasion which the masters in this school of wisdom bring to bear when words have no effect. As you know, they punish the recalcitrant with disenfranchisement, fines, and death.How could the private teaching of any sophist avail in counteracting theirs? It would be great folly even to try; for no instruction aiming at an ideal contrary to the training they give has ever produced, or will ever produce, a different type of character -- on the level, that is to say, of common humanity....[Y]ou may be sure that, in the present state of society, any character that escapes and comes to good can only have been saved by some miraculous interposition.3
Let us begin with the power of the surrounding culture.
Much like Resh Lakish, Plato offers the social psychological insight
that the overwhelming majority of individuals will prove incapable of
resisting the voice of the culture that surrounds them: in the typical
case, their values, their beliefs, indeed, their very perceptions will
tend to mirror those of the surrounding culture. To be sure, some
individuals may at times find themselves in social contexts (like
certain educational or religious settings) that enable them to take a
step back from the culture's norms and to apprehend and affirm moral
values that diverge from the culture's drift; but such counter-cultural
values are unlikely to survive in a meaningful way when these
individuals re-enter day-to-day life in the culture.
Viewed against the background of Nazi Germany and some of
the other horrors of the twentieth century, Plato's suggestion that an
individual is unlikely to maintain his or her value- commitments and
moral givens in the face of a surrounding culture that represents and
rewards different values rings all-too-true; and it may threaten to
engulf us in pessimism concerning the human future. For this reason, it
is important to note that Plato's perspective is not as pessimistic as
one might think at first. Note, first, that along with its darker
implications Plato's insight concerning the power of culture to shape
our outlook and conduct also carries the more comforting implication
that if the culture surrounding us embodies and rewards conformity to
desirable social norms, it will tend to call forth conduct in the
individual that is coherent with these norms; it can lead us to behave
much better than we otherwise would, stilling or in any case muting less
desirable impulses that might, in the absence of the culture's pull,
lead us to reprehensible conduct.
It is, secondly, noteworthy that Plato qualifies his
claims concerning the power of culture over the individual in an
important respect which is worthy of careful attention; for he intimates
that there is one kind of person who may be capable of withstanding the
culture's pull! Who is this exceptional individual? It is the person
who, having been born with the right native endowment, has also been
properly brought up. A sound education in childhood offers, Plato
suggests, a measure of protection in adulthood against the
countervailing power of the culture!
This sounds like a very promising qualification of
Plato's general view; but, as we shall see, it proves much less hopeful
than one might initially think. The reason for this is that, for Plato,
a proper up-bringing is impossible in the absence of a morally adequate
cultural environment. And this brings us face-to-face with the problem
of early childhood education as understood by Plato.
For if it is true that adults are powerfully influenced
towards conformity with the culture that surrounds them, all the more so
young children! In their case, the surrounding culture does not
challenge and overpower their pre-existing values and dispositions, for
these do not yet exist; rather, the culture creates these values and
dispositions! Hence, Plato's insistence that the culture that surrounds
young children in the form of real and fictional role-models represent
ideals of conduct that are proper to a human being.
Then we must compel our poets, on pain of expulsion, to make their poetry the express image of noble character; we must also supervise craftsmen of every kind and forbid them to leave the stamp of baseness, license, meanness, unseemliness, on painting and sculpture or building...We would not have our Guardians grow up among representations of moral deformity, as in some foul pasture where, day after day, feeding on every poisonous weed they would, little by little gather insensibly a mass of corruption in their very souls. Rather we must seek out those craftsmen whose instincts guides them to whatsoever is lovely and gracious; so that our young men, dwelling in a wholesome climate, may drink in good from every quarter, whence, like a breeze bearing health from happy regions, some influence from noble works constantly falls upon eye and ear from childhood upward, and imperceptibly draws them into sympathy and harmony with the beauty of reason, whose impress they take.4
Thus, Jerusalem and Athens speak with one voice on the
question of the role of culture in the moral life: culture is
enormously powerful, tending to shape individual human beings in its
image. Embedded in this view is a sharp critique of those who hold that
"moral education", understood as formal classes designed to promote
moral growth, has the power to nurture moral attitudes, dispositions,
and sensibilities that improve on what day-to-day life in the culture
encourages. How quickly, says Socrates, will the learning acquired at
the hands of a teacher dissolve in the face of the allure and the
threats presented by the crowd (the culture!). Do not, then, expect
much help from courses in ethics designed to stimulate moral growth;
and do not expect much from listening to, and even being temporarily
moved by, the stirring insights of a moral sage. Such influences do not
amount to very much so long as they are incoherent with the moral
messages being forcefully and continuously communicated by the cultural
environment.5
It follows from this analysis that rather than trying to
strengthen direct instruction in the schools, our efforts should be
directed towards weaving around the children of the community a cultural
totality that will nurture them with images of moral goodness which
will seep deeply and enduringly into their souls. When we do this, says
Plato,
rhythm and music sink seep into the recesses of the soul and take the strongest hold there, bringing that grace of body and mind which is only to be found in one who is brought up in the right way. Moreover, a proper training in this kind makes a man quick to perceive any defect or ugliness in art or in nature. Such deformity will rightly disgust him. Approving all that is lovely, he will welcome it home with joy into his soul and, nourished thereby, grow into a man of a noble spirit (Plato, 1966, p. 90).
Unfortunately, this solution is itself seriously
problematic: for it would appear to be naively unrealistic to think that
we have the capacity to reshape the larger culture in such a way that
the child is surrounded and nurtured by a worthy moral ideal; for better
and/or for worse, we are far from knowing how to re-shape cultural
attitudes and dispositions in accordance with our wishes. Indeed, those
who seek the kind of cultural transformation that is being suggested as
a condition of adequate moral education often turn to education to
launch this transformation.
We have, it would appear, a chicken-and-egg problem:
education is the key to the transformation of the culture's attitudes
regarding morality; but, if Plato is right, the effectiveness of such
education depends on a culture that supports the message delivered by
educational institutions. Is there a way out of this vicious -- a term
particularly appropriate, give our subject-matter -- circle?
An Approach to the Problem
To my way of thinking, there may -- and I use the word
"may" deliberately to signify something short of full confidence -- be a
way out of this dilemma. This way out is grounded in the insight that
schools and families are not just vehicles of "direct instruction", but
are themselves cultures. That is, they are social institutions
in which are embedded a rich array of norms, customs, and ways of
thinking. While it may true that schools, thought of as vehicles of
direct instruction, are not in a position to compete with the beliefs
and values that suffuse the larger culture, it may be that the culture
of the school, if organized around a moral vision that improves on what
is available in the larger culture, would prove a worthy competitor.
This distinction between schools as vehicles of direct
instruction and schools as cultures and the suggestion that the power of
schools as educating institutions lies largely in their influence as
cultures are forcefully articulated by John Dewey in his classic book Democracy and Education.
Commenting on the desirability of bringing about a culture in which
work is so organized that 1) a better fit obtains between aptitudes and
interests, on the one hand, and occupational role, on the other, and 2)
workers experience work as an arena in which to grow and to contribute
to the life of the community, Dewey turns to education as the path
towards this ideal. But in doing so, he explicitly disavows the
suggestion that education can accomplish this mission via direct
instruction. He writes:
Success or failure [in achieving a more adequately organized society] depends more upon the adoption of educational methods calculated to effect the change than upon anything else. For the change is essentially a change in the quality of mental disposition - an educative change. This does not mean that we can change character and mind by direct instruction, apart from a change in industrial and political conditions. Such a conception contradicts our basic idea that character and mind are attitudes of participative response in social affairs. But it does mean that we may produce in schools a projection in type of the society we should like to realize, and by forming minds in accord with it gradually modify the larger and more recalcitrant features of adult society.6What this means concretely for Dewey is that it would be futile to attempt to nurture, say, the spirit of social cooperation or the expectation that work is an arena for personal growth through any kind of direct instruction. There is, however, some likelihood of success if such values are woven into the very fabric, or organization, of day-to-day life in the school community, so that students encounter and absorb them as a matter-of-fact by-product of participating in the life of this community.
More generally, so long as the power of education to
shape basic moral beliefs and dispositions is identified with isolated
efforts to impart skills, understandings, and insights, there is little
reason to think it can compete with the larger culture that surrounds
the child -- especially if the cultures of educating institutions
themselves don't cohere with the contents of direct instruction. But
the moment we begin thinking of educating institutions as themselves
forms of culture in which the child is immersed, the situation changes
dramatically. Of course, one should not be naive about our ability
shape the ethos of a school-culture in accordance with our aspirations;
this too, as many an educational innovator and reformer will attest, can
be most difficult. Nonetheless, it is significantly more manageable
than the effort to directly transform the culture of the larger
community. And if the culture of the school-community can thus be
shaped, there is reason to hope that it will influence the young in ways
that will endure even in the face of a larger culture that is at
variance with the school-based dispositions and attitudes that they are
acquiring.
"There is reason to hope" -- but hope is not the same as
certainty or even great confidence. Imagine a school-community that
successfully embodies a culture that is at one with our highest moral
aspirations, and that throughout the life of this school -- in the
teachers, in the curriculum, in the hallways, in the lunchroom, on the
bulletin boards, etc. -- these moral aspirations live as social reality.
It remains an open question whether a child who goes through such a
school but continues to inhabit a larger culture that is at variance
with the school- culture will be decisively influenced by the
school-culture, rather than by the larger culture; and skeptics may also
wonder whether whatever good is accomplished in such an environment
will rapidly wash-out when graduates enter an adult world that is
unsupportive and punishing of the attitudes and dispositions encouraged
by the school. Such doubts are important and serve to caution us
against the kind of naive optimism that might lead us to hold that the
school can solve our problems.
But if, as just suggested, it is appropriate to avoid a
dogmatic conviction that schools are adequate to the challenge of
nurturing moral sensibilities and dispositions that challenge what is
the norm in the larger society, it is also important to avoid assuming
in advance that because of the concerns just raised schools are
necessarily powerless in this arena. There is no strong empirical basis
for such a view, and it is a view which discourages the very
educational experiments that have the potential to give us data that
will speak to this question.
There is also an additional (and very different kind of)
consideration that augurs well for the power of the school relative to
the larger culture. The suggestion that the larger culture will
overpower whatever the child learns through the culture of the school
may be built on an assumption which, though not identified and
challenged in this discussion, is, at least in our own society,
questionable. This is the assumption that the "the larger culture" is
singular rather than made up of multiple voices. While this may be
reasonably true of some cultures, it is arguable that in an open,
multi-cultural society like our own the child encounters a multitude of
cultural voices in the course of growing up, many of which are at
cross-purposes. Because the effect of these voices may be, if not to
cancel each other out, at least to weaken each one, the voice of the
school-culture, if it represents a compelling moral outlook in a
consistent way over many years, may prove very powerful -- in the same
way even a small minority coalition may powerfully affect the course of a
society if various other and possibly much larger political parties
cancel each other out.7
But even if this question concerning the power of
educational institutions relative to that of the larger culture can be
satisfactorily addressed, it must be noted that there are other
significant questions in need of addressing that I have largely bypassed
in this discussion. For example: 1) is it even possible to develop an
educational environment that is radically at variance with the larger
culture of the community? And assuming it is possible to develop a few
demonstration-sites of this kind, is it realistic to imagine such
institutions on a mass-scale in a country like the United States? 2)
Even if principle we agree that schools can and should be created that
are organized around a moral ideal that is different from what is
accepted in the larger culture, what is this moral ideal -- and who in a
democratic society that is grounded in the Constitution and that is
home to heterogeneous groups representing a diversity of moral outlook
should be empowered to determine educational policy in this area?
Though the beyond the scope of this paper, such questions are important
and need to occupy an important place in our communal and educational
agenda.
Notes
1 Hayim Nachman Bialik, and Yeshoshua Ravnitzky, The Book of Legends (New York: Schocken Books, 1992), p. 27.
2
"Noah walked with God (Gen. 6:9). R[abbi] Judah said: The phrasing may
be understood from the parable of a king who had two sons, one grown up
ad the other a child. To the child he said, Walk with me; but to the adult, Walk before me. Likewise to Abraham whose [spiritual] strength was great, he said, "Because you are whole-hearted, walk before me" (Gen. 17:1). But to Noah, whose [spiritual] strength was feeble, Scripture says, "Noah walked with God." Cited in Bialik and Ravnitzky, ibid., p. 27.
3 Plato's Republic, trans. by F. M.Cornford (New York: Oxford University Press, 1966), pp. 199-200.
4 Plato's Republic, ibid., p. 90. In his commentary on the Republic, Allan Bloom offers a contemporary statement of the Platonic view:
"Men's views about the highest beings and their choice of heroes are decisive for the tone of their lives. He who believes in the Olympian gods is a very different man from the one who believes in the Biblical God, just as the man who admires Achilles is different from the one who admires Moses or Jesus. The different men see very different things in the world and, although they may partake of a common human nature, they develop very different aspects of that nature; they hardly seem to be of the same species, so little do they agree about what is important in life...If poetry is so powerful, its character must be a primary concern of the legislator." Allan Bloom, "Plato's Republic: An Interpretive Essay," in The Republic 0f Plato, trans. by Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1968), p. 351.
5
Though it is beyond the scope of this paper to discuss contemporary
discussions of the influence of culture on the development and
expression of our character, it is noteworthy that the perspective I
have identified with Jerusalem and Athens is generally at one with the
findings of contemporary child development and social psychology.
6 John Dewey, Democracy and Education (New York: Macmillan Company, 1916), p. 370.
7
I am indebted to Francis Schrag and Amy Shuffelton for calling my
attention, in an earlier draft, to the fact that American culture is
more plural than my account suggested; and this paragraph is intended to
call the reader's attention to this point. While this is an important
point to consider, I want to suggest that within the diversity of
cultural influences a human being encounters in American society, there
may nonetheless be certain voices representing particular values that
speak very loud across these differences. To this extent, it would not
be the case that the presence of multiple cultural voices in American
society would operate to increase the strength of the school-culture.
No comments:
Post a Comment